

|
November 1993
Reverse Racism,
or How the Pot Got to Call the Kettle Black
In America "whites once set themselves apart from blacks and claimed privileges
for themselves while denying them to others," the author writes. "Now, on the
basis of race, blacks are claiming special status and reserving for themselves
privileges they deny to others. Isn't one as bad as the other? The answer is
no"
by Stanley Fish
I take my text from George Bush, who, in an address to the United Nations on
September 23, 1991, said this of the UN resolution equating Zionism with
racism: "Zionism . . . is the idea that led to the creation of a home for the
Jewish people. . . . And to equate Zionism with the intolerable sin of racism
is to twist history and forget the terrible plight of Jews in World War II and
indeed throughout history." What happened in the Second World War was that six
million Jews were exterminated by people who regarded them as racially inferior
and a danger to Aryan purity. What happened after the Second World War was that
the survivors of that Holocaust established a Jewish state--that is, a state
centered on Jewish history, Jewish values, and Jewish traditions: in short, a
Jewocentric state. What President Bush objected to was the logical sleight of
hand by which these two actions were declared equivalent because they were both
expressions of racial exclusiveness. Ignored, as Bush said, was the historical
difference between them--the difference between a program of genocide and the
determination of those who escaped it to establish a community in which they
would be the makers, not the victims, of the laws.
Only if racism is thought of as something that occurs principally in the mind,
a falling-away from proper notions of universal equality, can the desire of a
victimized and terrorized people to band together be declared morally identical
to the actions of their would-be executioners. Only when the actions of the two
groups are detached from the historical conditions of their emergence and given
a purely abstract description can they be made interchangeable. Bush was saying
to the United Nations, "Look, the Nazis' conviction of racial superiority
generated a policy of systematic genocide; the Jews' experience of centuries of
persecution in almost every country on earth generated a desire for a homeland
of their own. If you manage somehow to convince yourself that these are the
same, it is you, not the Zionists, who are morally confused, and the reason you
are morally confused is that you have forgotten history."
A KEY DISTINCTION
WHAT I want to say, following Bush's reasoning, is that a similar forgetting of
history has in recent years allowed some people to argue, and argue
persuasively, that affirmative action is reverse racism. The very phrase
Reverse Racism contains the argument in exactly the form to which Bush
objected: In this country whites once set themselves apart from blacks and
claimed privileges for themselves while denying them to others. Now, on the
basis of race, blacks are claiming special status and reserving for themselves
privileges they deny to others. Isn't one as bad as the other? The answer is
no. One can see why by imagining that it is not 1993 but 1955, and that we are
in a town in the South with two more or less distinct communities, one white
and one black. No doubt each community would have a ready store of dismissive
epithets, ridiculing stories, self-serving folk myths, and expressions of plain
hatred, all directed at the other community, and all based in racial hostility.
Yet to regard their respective racisms--if that is the word--as equivalent
would be bizarre, for the hostility of one group stems not from any wrong done
to it but from its wish to protect its ability to deprive citizens of their
voting rights, to limit access to educational institutions, to prevent entry
into the economy except at the lowest and most menial levels, and to force
members of the stigmatized group to ride in the back of the bus. The hostility
of the other group is the result of these actions, and whereas hostility and
racial anger are unhappy facts wherever they are found, a distinction must
surely be made between the ideological hostility of the oppressors and the
experience-based hostility of those who have been oppressed.
Not to make that distinction is, adapting George Bush's words, to twist history
and forget the terrible plight of African-Americans in the more than 200 years
of this country's existence. Moreover, to equate the efforts to remedy that
plight with the actions that produced it is to twist history even further.
Those efforts, designed to redress the imbalances caused by long-standing
discrimination, are called affirmative action; to argue that affirmative
action, which gives preferential treatment to disadvantaged minorities as part
of a plan to achieve social equality, is no different from the policies that
created the disadvantages in the first place is a travesty of reasoning.
Reverse Racism is a cogent description of affirmative action only if one
considers the cancer of racism to be morally and medically indistinguishable
from the therapy we apply to it. A cancer is an invasion of the body's
equilibrium, and so is chemotherapy; but we do not decline to fight the disease
because the medicine we employ is also disruptive of normal functioning. Strong
illness, strong remedy: the formula is as appropriate to the health of the body
politic as it is to that of the body proper.
At this point someone will always say, "But two wrongs don't make a right; if
it was wrong to treat blacks unfairly, it is wrong to give blacks preference
and thereby treat whites unfairly." This objection is just another version of
the forgetting and rewriting of history. The work is done by the adverb
"unfairly," which suggests two more or less equal parties, one of whom has been
unjustly penalized by an incompetent umpire. But blacks have not simply been
treated unfairly; they have been subjected first to decades of slavery, and
then to decades of second-class citizenship, widespread legalized
discrimination, economic persecution, educational deprivation, and cultural
stigmatization. They have been bought, sold, killed, beaten, raped, excluded,
exploited, shamed, and scorned for a very long time. The word "unfair" is
hardly an adequate description of their experience, and the belated gift of
"fairness" in the form of a resolution no longer to discriminate against them
legally is hardly an adequate remedy for the deep disadvantages that the prior
discrimination has produced. When the deck is stacked against you in more ways
than you can even count, it is small consolation to hear that you are now free
to enter the game and take your chances.
A TILTED FIELD
THE same insincerity and hollowness of promise infect another formula that is
popular with the anti-affirmative-action crowd: the formula of the level
playing field. Here the argument usually takes the form of saying "It is
undemocratic to give one class of citizens advantages at the expense of other
citizens; the truly democratic way is to have a level playing field to which
everyone has access and where everyone has a fair and equal chance to succeed
on the basis of his or her merit." Fine words--but they conceal the facts of
the situation as it has been given to us by history: the playing field is
already tilted in favor of those by whom and for whom it was constructed in the
first place. If mastery of the requirements for entry depends upon immersion in
the cultural experiences of the mainstream majority, if the skills that make
for success are nurtured by institutions and cultural practices from which the
disadvantaged minority has been systematically excluded, if the language and
ways of comporting oneself that identify a player as "one of us" are alien to
the lives minorities are forced to live, then words like "fair" and "equal" are
cruel jokes, for what they promote and celebrate is an institutionalized
unfairness and a perpetuated inequality. The playing field is already tilted,
and the resistance to altering it by the mechanisms of affirmative action is in
fact a determination to make sure that the present imbalances persist as long
as possible.
One way of tilting the field is the Scholastic Aptitude Test. This test figures
prominently in Dinesh D'Souza's book Illiberal Education (1991), in which one
finds many examples of white or Asian students denied admission to colleges and
universities even though their SAT scores were higher than the scores of some
others--often African-Americans--who were admitted to the same institution.
This, D'Souza says, is evidence that as a result of affirmative-action policies
colleges and universities tend "to depreciate the importance of merit criteria
in admissions." D'Souza's assumption--and it is one that many would share--is
that the test does in fact measure merit, with merit understood as a quality
objectively determined in the same way that body temperature can be objectively
determined.
In fact, however, the test is nothing of the kind. Statistical studies have
suggested that test scores reflect income and socioeconomic status. It has been
demonstrated again and again that scores vary in relation to cultural
background; the test's questions assume a certain uniformity in educational
experience and lifestyle and penalize those who, for whatever reason, have had
a different experience and lived different kinds of lives. In short, what is
being measured by the SAT is not absolutes like native ability and merit but
accidents like birth, social position, access to libraries, and the opportunity
to take vacations or to take SAT prep courses.
Furthermore, as David Owen notes in None of the Above: Behind the Myth of
Scholastic Aptitude (1985), the "correlation between SAT scores and college
grades . . . is lower than the correlation between weight and height; in other
words you would have a better chance of predicting a person's height by looking
at his weight than you would of predicting his freshman grades by looking only
at his SAT scores." Everywhere you look in the SAT story, the claims of
fairness, objectivity, and neutrality fall away, to be replaced by suspicions
of specialized measures and unfair advantages.
Against this background a point that in isolation might have a questionable
force takes on a special and even explanatory resonance: the principal deviser
of the test was an out-and-out racist. In 1923 Carl Campbell Brigham published
a book called A Study of American Intelligence, in which, as Owen notes, he
declared, among other things, that we faced in America "a possibility of racial
admixture . . . infinitely worse than that faced by any European country today,
for we are incorporating the Negro into our racial stock, while all of Europe
is comparatively free of this taint." Brigham had earlier analyzed the Army
Mental Tests using classifications drawn from another racist text, Madison
Grant's The Passing of the Great Race, which divided American society into four
distinct racial strains, with Nordic, blue-eyed, blond people at the pinnacle
and the American Negro at the bottom. Nevertheless, in 1925 Brigham became a
director of testing for the College Board, and developed the SAT. So here is
the great SAT test, devised by a racist in order to confirm racist assumptions,
measuring not native ability but cultural advantage, an uncertain indicator of
performance, an indicator of very little except what money and social privilege
can buy. And it is in the name of this mechanism that we are asked to reject
affirmative action and reaffirm "the importance of merit criteria in
admissions."
THE REALITY OF DISCRIMINATION
NEVERTHELESS, there is at least one more card to play against affirmative
action, and it is a strong one. Granted that the playing field is not level and
that access to it is reserved for an already advantaged elite, the
disadvantages suffered by others are less racial--at least in 1993--than
socioeconomic. Therefore shouldn't, as D'Souza urges, "universities . . .
retain their policies of preferential treatment, but alter their criteria of
application from race to socioeconomic disadvantage," and thus avoid the
unfairness of current policies that reward middle-class or affluent blacks at
the expense of poor whites? One answer to this question is given by D'Souza
himself when he acknowledges that the overlap between minority groups and the
poor is very large--a point underscored by the former Secretary of Education
Lamar Alexander, who said, in response to a question about funds targeted for
black students, "Ninety-eight percent of race-specific scholarships do not
involve constitutional problems." He meant, I take it, that 98 percent of
race-specific scholarships were also scholarships to the economically
disadvantaged.
Still, the other two percent--nonpoor, middle-class, economically favored
blacks--are receiving special attention on the basis of disadvantages they do
not experience. What about them? The force of the question depends on the
assumption that in this day and age race could not possibly be a serious
disadvantage to those who are otherwise well positioned in the society. But the
lie was given dramatically to this assumption in a 1991 broadcast of the ABC
program PrimeTime Live. In a stunning fifteen-minute segment reporters and a
camera crew followed two young men of equal education, cultural sophistication,
level of apparent affluence, and so forth around St. Louis, a city where
neither was known. The two differed in only a single respect: one was white,
the other black. But that small difference turned out to mean everything. In a
series of encounters with shoe salesmen, record-store employees, rental agents,
landlords, employment agencies, taxicab drivers, and ordinary citizens, the
black member of the pair was either ignored or given a special and suspicious
attention. He was asked to pay more for the same goods or come up with a larger
down payment for the same car, was turned away as a prospective tenant, was
rejected as a prospective taxicab fare, was treated with contempt and
irritation by clerks and bureaucrats, and in every way possible was made to
feel inferior and unwanted.
The inescapable conclusion was that alike though they may have been in almost
all respects, one of these young men, because he was black, would lead a
significantly lesser life than his white counterpart: he would be housed less
well and at greater expense; he would pay more for services and products when
and if he was given the opportunity to buy them; he would have difficulty
establishing credit; the first emotions he would inspire on the part of many
people he met would be distrust and fear; his abilities would be discounted
even before he had a chance to display them; and, above all, the treatment he
received from minute to minute would chip away at his self-esteem and
self-confidence with consequences that most of us could not even imagine. As
the young man in question said at the conclusion of the broadcast, "You walk
down the street with a suit and tie and it doesn't matter. Someone will make
determinations about you, determinations that affect the quality of your
life."
Of course, the same determinations are being made quite early on by
kindergarten teachers, grade school principals, high school guidance
counselors, and the like, with results that cut across socioeconomic lines and
place young black men and women in the ranks of the disadvantaged no matter
what the bank accounts of their parents happen to show. Racism is a cultural
fact, and although its effects may to some extent be diminished by
socioeconomic variables, those effects will still be sufficiently great to
warrant the nation's attention and thus the continuation of affirmative-action
policies. This is true even of the field thought to be dominated by blacks and
often cited as evidence of the equal opportunities society now affords them. I
refer, of course, to professional athletics. But national self-congratulation
on this score might pause in the face of a few facts: A minuscule number of
African-Americans ever receive a paycheck from a professional team. Even though
nearly 1,600 daily newspapers report on the exploits of black athletes, they
employ only seven full-time black sports columnists. Despite repeated pledges
and resolutions, major-league teams have managed to put only a handful of
blacks and Hispanics in executive positions.
WHY ME?
WHEN all is said and done, however, one objection to affirmative action is
unanswerable on its own terms, and that is the objection of the individual who
says, "Why me? Sure, discrimination has persisted for many years, and I
acknowledge that the damage done has not been removed by changes in the law.
But why me? I didn't own slaves; I didn't vote to keep people on the back of
the bus; I didn't turn water hoses on civil-rights marchers. Why, then, should
I be the one who doesn't get the job or who doesn't get the scholarship or who
gets bumped back to the waiting list?"
I sympathize with this feeling, if only because in a small way I have had the
experience that produces it. I was recently nominated for an administrative
post at a large university. Early signs were encouraging, but after an interval
I received official notice that I would not be included at the next level of
consideration, and subsequently I was told unofficially that at some point a
decision had been made to look only in the direction of women and minorities.
Although I was disappointed, I did not conclude that the situation was
"unfair," because the policy was obviously not directed at me--at no point in
the proceedings did someone say, "Let's find a way to rule out Stanley Fish."
Nor was it directed even at persons of my race and sex--the policy was not
intended to disenfranchise white males. Rather, the policy was driven by other
considerations, and it was only as a by-product of those considerations--not as
the main goal--that white males like me were rejected. Given that the
institution in question has a high percentage of minority students, a very low
percentage of minority faculty, and an even lower percentage of minority
administrators, it made perfect sense to focus on women and minority
candidates, and within that sense, not as the result of prejudice, my whiteness
and maleness became disqualifications.
I can hear the objection in advance: "What's the difference? Unfair is unfair:
you didn't get the job; you didn't even get on the short list." The difference
is not in the outcome but in the ways of thinking that led up to the outcome.
It is the difference between an unfairness that befalls one as the unintended
effect of a policy rationally conceived and an unfairness that is pursued as an
end in itself. It is the difference between the awful unfairness of Nazi
extermination camps and the unfairness to Palestinian Arabs that arose from,
but was not the chief purpose of, the founding of a Jewish state.
THE NEW BIGOTRY
THE point is not a difficult one, but it is difficult to see when the
unfairness scenarios are presented as simple contrasts between two
decontextualized persons who emerge from nowhere to contend for a job or a
place in a freshman class. Here is student A; he has a board score of 1,300.
And here is student B; her board score is only 1,200, yet she is admitted and A
is rejected. Is that fair? Given the minimal information provided, the answer
is of course no. But if we expand our horizons and consider fairness in
relation to the cultural and institutional histories that have brought the two
students to this point, histories that weigh on them even if they are not the
histories' authors, then both the question and the answer suddenly grow more
complicated.
The sleight-of-hand logic that first abstracts events from history and then
assesses them from behind a veil of willed ignorance gains some of its
plausibility from another key word in the anti-affirmative-action lexicon. That
word is "individual," as in "The American way is to focus on the rights of
individuals rather than groups." Now, "individual" and "individualism" have
been honorable words in the American political vocabulary, and they have often
been well employed in the fight against various tyrannies. But like any other
word or concept, individualism can be perverted to serve ends the opposite of
those it originally served, and this is what has happened when in the name of
individual rights, millions of individuals are enjoined from redressing
historically documented wrongs. How is this managed? Largely in the same way
that the invocation of fairness is used to legitimize an institutionalized
inequality. First one says, in the most solemn of tones, that the protection of
individual rights is the chief obligation of society. Then one defines
individuals as souls sent into the world with equal entitlements as guaranteed
either by their Creator or by the Constitution. Then one pretends that nothing
has happened to them since they stepped onto the world's stage. And then one
says of these carefully denatured souls that they will all be treated in the
same way, irrespective of any of the differences that history has produced.
Bizarre as it may seem, individualism in this argument turns out to mean that
everyone is or should be the same. This dismissal of individual difference in
the name of the individual would be funny were its consequences not so serious:
it is the mechanism by which imbalances and inequities suffered by millions of
people through no fault of their own can be sanitized and even celebrated as
the natural workings of unfettered democracy.
"Individualism," "fairness," "merit"--these three words are continually
misappropriated by bigots who have learned that they need not put on a white
hood or bar access to the ballot box in order to secure their ends. Rather,
they need only clothe themselves in a vocabulary plucked from its historical
context and made into the justification for attitudes and policies they would
not acknowledge if frankly named.
Copyright © 1993 by Stanley Fish. All rights reserved.
|