The Case for Involuntary Commitment

By Jeffrey Goldberg

Like many others, I remain unconvinced that the Tucson shooting is mainly a story about incivility in politics. Jared Lee Loughner, by all accounts, appears to be deeply mentally ill, and mental illness seems to have taken hold of him before the rise of Sarah Palin. The story, so far at least, seems more about the way we as a society manage the violently mentally ill among us. Obviously, the Tucson shooting raises questions about one politically incendiary issue, gun control, but it also intersects with another: the argument overĀ  involuntary commitment of people judged to be mentally ill and dangerous to themselves and others. As William Galston points out (in a piece he acknowledges will infuriate some civil libertarians):

The story repeats itself, over and over. A single narrative connects the Unabomber, George Wallace shooter Arthur Bremmer, Reagan shooter John Hinckley, the Virginia Tech shooter--all mentally disturbed loners who needed to be committed and treated against their will. But the law would not permit it.

Starting in the 1970s, civil libertarians worked to eliminate involuntary commitment or, that failing, to raise the standards and burden of proof so high that few individuals would meet it. Important decisions by the Supreme Court and subordinate courts gave individuals new protections, including a constitutional right to refuse psychotropic medication. A few states have tried to push back in constitutionally acceptable ways, but efforts such as California's Laura's Law, designed to make it easier to force patients to take medication, have been stymied by civil rights concerns and lack of funding.


This article available online at:

http://www.theatlantic.com/national/archive/2011/01/the-case-for-involuntary-commitment/69299/